Praxis and the ends of action in Suárez

  1. González Ginocchio, David
Journal:
Anuario filosófico

ISSN: 0066-5215

Year of publication: 2017

Volume: 50

Issue: 2

Pages: 371-396

Type: Article

DOI: 10.15581/009.50.2.371-396 DIALNET GOOGLE SCHOLAR lock_openOpen access editor

More publications in: Anuario filosófico

Sustainable development goals

Abstract

I will try to show how Suárez’s model of praxis allows for the coordination of intellect and will to generate actions through the integration of ends. A special sense of causality is studied that adds a practical overlay to actions: while actions remain an external mode of the effect, they can be contingent insofar as they are produced by a free agent with particular ends in mind. I will argue that the appearance of these ends is only possible through a habitual understanding of praxis, which is a subjective consideration of reality as ‘operable’.

Bibliographic References

  • C. RAPP, Tackling Aristotle's Notion of the Will, "Philosophical Inquiry" 41/ 2-3 (2017) 67-79
  • S. EFTHYMIADIS, C. PANAYIDES, P. THANASSAS (eds.), Readings of Aristotle (Nicosia University Press, Nicosia, 2014) 51-69
  • A. M. SCHMITTER, Hume on the Emotions, en E. N. ZALTA (ed.), The Stanford En cyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition) 〈http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/emotions-17th18th/LD8Hume.html〉 (Last access: 24.XI.2015).
  • M. LECON, Metaphysics and Psychology of the Making of Law in Francisco Suárez, en K. BUNGE, M. FUCHS, D. SIMMERMACHER (eds.), The Concept of Law (lex) in the Moral and Political Thought of the 'School of Salamanca' (Brill, Leiden, 2016) 249-270.
  • J. B. SOUTH, Francisco Suárez on Imagination, "Vivarium" 39/1 (2001) 119-158.
  • Th. M. OSBORNE, Jr's recent systematic study, Human Action in Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus and William of Ockham (The Catholic University of America Press, Washington, D. C., 2014).
  • Th. GILBY, Summa theologiae vol. 17 (Cambridge University Press, 1964).
  • Th. WILLIAMS, Review of Thomas M. Osborne Jr., Human Action, "Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews", 16.VII.2014 (http://ntrda.me/1lfHeTQ). [Last access 23.XI.2015.]
  • C. GONZÁLEZ AYESTA, Duns Scotus on the Natural Will, "Vivarium" 50 (2012) 33-52.
  • E. STUMP, Obligations: From the Beginning to the Early Fourteenth Century, en N. KRETZMANN et al. (eds.), The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1982), ch. 16, Part A, 315-334.
  • S. DUMONT, The Origin of Scotus's Theory of Synchronic Contingency, "Modern Schoolman" 72 (1995) 149-167.
  • T. PINK, Suarez, Hobbes and the scholastic tradition in action theory, en T. PINK, M. STONE (eds.), The Will and Human Action: From Antiquity to the Present Day (Routledge, London, 2004) 127-153.
  • S. PENNER, "Final Causality: Suárez on the Priority of Final Causation" cit., 129.
  • A. VIGO, Intelecto, deseo y acción en Francisco Suárez, en J. CRUZ (ed.), Razón práctica y derecho. Cuestiones filosófico-jurídicas en el Siglo de Oro español (Eunsa, Pamplona, 2011) 15-23.
  • J.-P. COUJOU, Causalité libre et moralité de l'action chez Suárez, en C. GONZÁLEZ AYESTA, R. LÁZARO (eds.), Causality in Early Modern Philosophy (Georg Olms Verlag, Hildesheim, 2013) 89-98.
  • R. DARGE, Suárez' transzendentale Seinsauslegung und die Metaphysiktradition (Brill, Leiden, 2004) 313
  • C. GONZÁLEZ AYESTA, Sobre el "escotismo" de Suárez: el caso de la causalidad de la especie, en A. ECHAVARRÍA, J. F. FRANCK (eds.), La causalidad en la filosofía moderna (Servicio de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Navarra, Pamplona, 2012) 9-16.